Navigation: This page 'dooy.info/tc.html' ---> Main Page. HELP. Contact. About Page.

Dooyeweerd's Transcendental Critique

Dooyeweerd was convinced that theoretical thinking is neither absolute nor even neutral. In fact, is it even valid? After all, many practical people disdain theories as misleading and impractical. And yet the whole edifice of academia is built on it, and most in government, education, industry, commerce, and so on assume its validity. Dooyeweerd tried to address this conundrum.

Dooyeweerd's thought parallels that of thinkers like Polanyi, Habermas, Adorno and Kuhn, who also argued that theoretical thought is not neutral - but it goes beyond their thought and digs deeper. Polanyi spoke of personal knowledge, Habermas of 'human interests' and then power relations that distort ideal discourse, and Kuhn of paradigms. I believe these may all be derived from Dooyeweerd's ideas, or maybe explained by sthem, because Dooyeweerd's ideas cover the issues they do, and more besides.

Dooyeweerd was, in some ways, more radical than many thinkers in his critique of theoretical thought. Dooyeweerd critically examined theoretical thought in two ways. One showed that theoretical thought never has been neutral. The other showed that, by its very nature, it never could be neutral even in an ideal world, but theoretical thought always involves religious presuppositions.

Dooyeweerd first made an Immanent Critique of 2500 years of theoretical thought, mainly 'Western' though with some mention of Eastern cultures. He showed that theoretical thought has never been neutral, an authority on which we may absolutely rely. But the question remains, "Could it ever become neutral, absolutely authoritative?" To answer that question was the main purpose of his attempt Transcendental Critique. Transcendental critique tries to identify the conditions that universally need to be fulfilled in order for it to be so. Dooyeweerd found that theoretical thought can never be neutral, because of presuppositions we need to make in doing it.

Dooyeweerd found two ways of transcendental critique. Dooyeweerd recognised two types of theoretical thought - research in the various sciences, and thinking in philosophy - and his second way covers both. Both aim to contribute good theories to humanity's bodies of knowledge.

(Note: Transcendental critique is not the opposite of immanent critique. What is its opposite is transcendent critique, which criticises from outside.)

The aim of this page is to try to explain Dooyeweerd's transcendental critique of theoretical thought in ways that most people might understand; the way he and other philosophers have explained it makes it rather difficult.

Contents:

  • Criticisms of Dooyeweerd's Transcendental Critique


    Dooyeweerd's Approach To Transcendental Critique

    A transcendental critique of theoretical thought tries to uncover the conditions that make theoretical thought possible, by exploring its very nature - conditions that are always and everywhere necessary for it to be and occur.

    One rather unique feature of Dooyeweerd's approach is that, while many thinkers presuppose theoretical thought, its power and validity, even when trying to make a critique thereof, Dooyeweerd refused to do so. How can one make a valid critique if one begins by presupposing the outcome? Instead, Dooyeweerd presupposed the validity and power of pre-theoretical thought, as we employ it in everyday experience and engaging in all we do.

    So his transcendental critique begins with pre-theoretical experience.

    In fact, I have detected six things that characterize Dooyeweerd's approach:

    Even doing our thinking or research exhibits diverse aspects - not only the analytical / logical aspect, but also planning, social activity, believing and desiring, generosity or meanness, doing justice or injustice to the topic, and so on. (We can refer to the aspects that Dooyeweerd delineated, except that he did so using theoretical thought, so we must not presuppose them in critiquing theoretical thought!

    These resonate with the approach to research outlined in previous Chapters: transcendental critique is never absolute but always relative to one's starting-points.

    Geertsema [2021, 112] usefully distinguishes two phases of transcendental critique. At first, Dooyeweerd's main aim was to establish that theoretical thought cannot operate without religious presuppositions (this is his idea of non-neutrality). But then he expanded this because he believed it could help understand theoretical thought more generally and that it was a real contribution to philosophy as a whole. I have found it a real contribution to understanding scientific research, as I discuss in Basden 2019.

    On the Non-Neutrality of Theoretical Thinking

    With Habermas, Dooyeweerd believed that theoretical thinking 'distorts' our picture of the state of things but, while the implication of Habermas is that this distortion is an evil brought about by something external to rationality themselves (viz. by power relations), Dooyeweerd believed that it is in the very nature of theoretical thought to distort and that this distortion is not evil. As Clouser has suggested, it is like a thermometer placed into a liquid that changes the temperature of the thing it measures. Habermas had a notion of ideal rationality and ideal discourse which might never be realized but which emancipates us from the distortion, but Dooyeweerd believed that theoretical thinking would 'distort' knowledge even in its ideal.

    With Polanyi, Kuhn and others, Dooyeweerd believed that our personal viewpoint affects the process of our theoretical thinking, but he made a positive proposal that the nature of this viewpoint has a religious root, and is not merely logical or social in origin. Human beings, he believed, are inescapably religious beings (indeed, the whole of reality, even the mud in which trees grow, has a religious root). Our religious side is not, as positivists believed, something to suppress, but something to welcome and take account of. It is this that forms the basis of his transcendental critique.

    'The First Way of Critique'

    (For a fuller explanation of this, see Choi's account of the First Way.)

    The First Way of Critique is made on the basis of what philosophy is. On this basis, Dooyeweerd argued as follows:

    Since (or if we assume) science depends on philosophy, then it follows that scientific theoretical thinking also has a religious root.

    (Note: The human self and self-reflective critique also have a place in Dooyeweerd's argument, but they seem to have no clear part to play in this First Way, and perhaps this moved Dooyeweerd to find a 'second way of critique'. Choi includes them in his explanation of Way 1.)

    One can find elements of this in other thinkers. For example Bourdieu [Outline of a Theory of Practice, 1977], coming from anthropology, which will be faced with varied spheres of meaning, refers [p.2] to "limits inherent in his [the anthropologist's] point of view". However, the rest of Dooyeweerd's argument was criticised for taking one view of what philosophy is. So he sought a different way of transcendental critique.

    Need for Another Way of Critique

    Dooyeweerd published his First Way of critique in his (1930s) WdW. But critique of WdW led him to rethink and seek another way of critique, which led to his Second Way of critique below, which was published alongside the First Way in his (1955) NC. As Bruce Wearne put it in an email, "Dooyeweerd in NCTT admits that he had to refine his transcendental critique after WdW lest his philosophy simply endorse a dogmatic anti-dogmatism." However, before looking at his Second Way, it may be instructive to read a step-by-step reasoning he set out for the need for a another way of critique. This is Magnus Verbrugge's 1980 translation of what Dooyeweerd wrote in Part Three of the Reformatie en Scholastiek in de Wijsbegeerte, the first volume of which was published in 1949.

    How is philosophic thinking possible as theoretic thinking?

    [para 1] Our Cosmonomic Philosophy opens its transcendental critique with this question. But it directs itself to every possible philosophy - it is not restricted to a reformed philosophy. Thus this question first of all confronts current philosophy with a fundamental problem, since this philosophy starts from the assumption that theoretical thought is autonomous vis a vis faith. This is a "transcendental" problem since it concerns the boundaries of philosophy. It touches the pre-existing structure of theoretical philosophic thinking which first makes this thought possible.

    [para 2] Now this pre-existing structure itself cannot again be of a philosophic character. It is an idionomic[1] framework upon which all philosophic thought-activity rests. Philosophic thought must move within this framework if it is to maintain its philosophic character. As we have remarked earlier, such a framework is aprioristic. It is given beforehand and has general validity ie it rules philosophic thinking, regardless of the subjective starting point of the thinker.

    [para 3] Still, we can only examine this universally valid structural law of philosophic thought in the theoretical-philosophical attitude of thought. We may start out believing in its existence. But that does not yet disclose its real character to our scientific[2] insight. And that is exactly what we need.

    [para 4] We must discuss the question whether scientific[2] thought can indeed function without being bound to such a belief. But such a discussion is only possible if we give a scientific[2] account of the nature of philosophic thought. Thus, if philosophy wants to go to work critically it must start with directing its enquiry towards its own presuppositions.

    [para 5] In this enquiry we may not parade the dogma of the autonomy of theoretical reason as if it were a self-evident consequence of the structure of philosophic thought. For that would amount to a dogmatic elimination of the basic critical problem we formulated at the onset of this section.

    [para 6] Nor may we demand of the believers of this dogma to begin with abandoning it. For that too would amount to eliminating the transcendental problem of philosophy with a magic formula. That would simply replace the dogma of the autonomy of theoretical reason with the dogma that reason is determined by supra-theoretical presuppositions of faith. And, in that case, our critical insight into the nature and structure of philosophic thought would not be enriched in the slightest. We would merely end up with a confrontation of dogmatic points of view.

    [para 7] No, when we begin our critical enquiry, we may demand of no thinker that he abandon any dogmatic conviction. We may only postulate one strict condition for a truly critical attitude of thought. The enquirer must be prepared to put aside the dogmatic presupposition postulating the autonomy of philosophy to be of a purely theoretical, scientific[2] character. For only this prejudice stands in the way of a critical investigation of the basic problem we have formulated. It merely passes a dogma, a religious conviction that cannot be reasoned, for a scientific[2], theoretical judgement.

    [para 8] The Cosmonomic Philosophy does not claim that we could begin a transcendental critique of philosophic thought independent of a dogmatic religious conviction. For if it did, we ourselves would have to start with accepting the autonomy of theoretic reason as a purely theoretic prejudice. It would then pass that for a criterium as to whether further enquiry is scientific[2] or not. To the contrary. it openly admits that our philosophy starts its transcendental theoretical critique from the Christian religious standpoint. But it does remain critical in this. For it sharply distinguishes its religious conviction from any essentially scientific[2] judgement from the start.

    [para 9] In other words, it does not camouflage its starting point. It rather begins with a sharp, critical distinction between theoretic judgement and supra-theoretic prejudice. Thus no-one can become the victim of an artfully camouflaged trap in following our enquiry into the transcendental problems that underlie philosophy. One can be confident that no religious judgement will be paraded here as an essentially scientific [2] thesis. This transcendental critique serves just this very purpose - it forces the thinker to account to himself of the true nature of the prejudice he starts with.

    That is, it seemed that the argument in the First Way depends to some extent on accepting certain presuppositions or dogma, whereas in the Second Way Dooyeweerd was seeking a way of understanding philosophy that could apply to philosophers of any kind, whatever their religious starting points.

    'The Second Way of Critique'

    (For a fuller explanation of this, see Choi's account of the Second Way. For a clarification by Dooyeweerd of his notion of Gegenstand, as a response to criticism by Strauss, see Glenn Friessen's translation of Dooyeweerd's last publication. Also, I now understand Dooyeweerd's second way of Critique in a different way and so my original rendering contains what I now believe are some faults, nevertheless, I retain my original rendering below.)

    The Second Way of Critique is made on the basis of the very nature of theoretical thought itself. It employs neo-Kantian ways of thinking and, to some extent, the neo-Kantian view of what theoretical thinking is. (Though he disagreed with the neo-Kantians on content and presuppositions, Dooyeweerd believed that they did at least ask the right questions.) Another explanation of this 'second way' is given by Clouser, which some find easier to understand.

    Dooyeweerd argued [NC, I,p.34ff.] that to justify taking a theoretical attitude a philosophy must face three basic (transcendental) problems, for each of which he posed a question and provided an answer, which makes the next problem necessary. This revealed that theoretical thought is inescapably religious at its root, rather than neutral - and that what religious presupposition we make determines the way we treat theoretical thinking and work it out.

    By 'religious' he did not mean relating to any particular religion or creed, explaining [I,p.57]:

    "To the question, what is understood here by religion? I reply: the innate impulse of human selfhood to direct itself toward the true or toward a pretended absolute Origin of all temporal diversity of meaning, which it finds focused concentrically in itself."

    Here is his three transcendental basic problems in tabular form.

    Basic Problem More Question Answer
    1. Concerning theoretical versus pre-theoretical attitude of thought [NC,I,p.38-44] Theoretical attitude involves Gegenstand, an antithetic attitude in which we stand over against the world we are studying and 'abstract' from it that which is meaningful to us [NC,I,p.39]. The pre-theoretical attitude knows of no Gegenstand [NC.II,p.431]; we are engaged within the world and all ways of being meaningful. "What do we abstract in the antithetic attitude of theoretic thought from the structures of empirical reality as these structures are given to naïve experience? And how is this abstraction possible?" [[NC,I,p.41]"

    "What is the continuous bond of coherence between the logical and the non-logical aspects of our experience from which these aspects are abstracted in the theoretical attitude?" Twilight, 11]

    We abstract an aspect of the world, one way in which what we study might be meaningful to us. One aspect of our functioning as human beings provides us with data which we set against the analytical aspect of our functioning. [NC,I,p.54]
    Note that Dooyeweerd criticised Kant and others for restricting the generation of data to our sensitive functioning, and opened up the possibility that functioning in any aspect could do so.
    What this implies is that even experimentation can be wrong, because, in focusing on aspects we deem relevant, we always ignore other aspects. R. P. Feynman said "It doesn't matter how beautiful your theory is, it doesn't matter how smart you are. If it doesn't agree with experiment, it's wrong." It may indeed be wrong - but even the experiment might be wrong, and occasionally a theory that takes the ignored aspects into account might be more right than Feynman realised!
    Whichever aspect generates the data (sensitive or other) the aspects have been split asunder. This raises the next transcendental problem:
    2. Concerning the human thinker who reunites aspects [NC,I,p.45-52] The aspects have been set apart, especially the analytical aspect and another aspect (its Gegenstand). We must be sure that this is valid and possible, so must understand the relationship between them. If aspects X and Y have a Gegenstand relationship then there is no over-arching framework that can bring them together when the relationship is activiated. And it is not valid for this to be done by either X or Y. For example, why do we assume that what our sensory or emotional functioning generates can be validly manipulated by analytical activity? This is a problem that Kant recognised, and he called the theoretical synthesis.

    What is this synthesis? An example of what Dooyeweerd understand by it is given in Twilight, p15, "Even a so-called formal logic cannot do without a synthesis between the logical aspect and that of symbolic signification, which are by no means identical." That is, the thinker operates in at least the analytical and lingual aspects as they formulate their findings, which impose different laws and rationalities.

    "From what standpoint can we reunite synthetically the logical and the non-logical aspects of experience which were set apart in opposition to each other in the theoretical attitude?" [NC,I,p.45]

    "What is the central reference point in our consciousness from which the synthesis can start?" [Twilight, 15]
    Note that 'logical' means 'analytical' and 'non-logical' refers to the Gegenstand aspect.

    It is only the human being who thinks who can determine how the two aspects are brought together.
    This means that all good philosophies must include an account of the human being who thinks - and this account must be consistent with all the rest of the philosophy. Specifically, it is not enough for a philosophy to have an account only of theoretical thought in the abstract and an ontology of the world. For example, in formal logic, how do we function in both analytical and lingual aspects in coherence, and on what grounds may that multi-aspectual functioning yield valid findings? Older philosophies failed in this regard; more recent philosophies such as by Foucault and Habermas (as well as Dooyeweerd) include an explicit account of the human thinker.
    3. Concering the Origin of Meaning [NC,I,p.52ff.] Above the portals of philosophy is written "Philosopher, know thyself". Such self-knowledge must include an account of both the human self as that which can integrate different aspects, and human functioning in the world. It is not enough to provide a psychological or sociological account of the activity of human thinking, for example. Habermas' account of the human is limited in this regard: to social theory. There is a need for critical self-reflection. "How is this critical self-reflection, this concentric direction of theoretical thought to the I-ness, possible, and what is its true character?" [NC,I,p.52]

    "How is the concentric direction of theoretical thought towards the eco possible, and what is its source?" Twilight, 17]

    Two parts to answer:

    1. Critical self-reflection requires concentration upon what we conceive of as the Origin of Meaning, because "self-knowledge in the last analysis appears to be dependent on knowledge of God" or of something that we treat as God [NC,I,p.55]. This is religious rather than theoretical knowledge.

    2. This religious self-knowledge is not just individual but super-individual, pervading a community. Community belief is guided by a ground-motive. When a proposal for new generic knowledge, on the basis of the first two questions above, is to be critiqued by the community, their basis for critique is what they find meaningful, and when what one person finds meaningful is critiqued by another, then that critique is judged by reference to what everyone tacitly agrees is the Origin of Meaning.

    So theoretical thought cannot escape having a religious root because it presupposes an Origin of Meaning, in order to reunite aspects that were set apart in the antithetical Gegenstand relationship. Thus theoretical thought has been guided at a deep level by four ground-motives of Western thought; these have determined what we count as basic reality, what we deem to be 'proper' ways of thinking, and the process of that thinking.

    On Origin of Meaning

    The origin of meaning seems to be that to which we in a field appeal when we want to radically question a prevailing paradigm and find an alternative. If so, origin of meaning is the ground-motive presuppositions we hold about what is ultimately meaningful, what it all boils down to. Pluralistic ground-motives like CFR presuppose multiple modalities of meaning (aspects) and so an alternative paradigm may be sought in a different aspect.

    In dualistic ground-motives, which seem to prevail today, and offer two modalities of meaning, their two poles, the alternative is the opposing pole. Usually the two poles are seen in normative terms, one Good, to be adhered to, the other Evil, to be avoided. Examples:

    The process of choosing the other pole is not logical so much as the other pole offering the promise of escape from the evil we currently feel entrapped in the current paradigm. In Western thought at least, this is not wholly one-or-the-other, but deep down we are pulled in one direction or another.

    Might it be that the nuance felt in some Western thought comes from the minority influence it has received from the pluralistic ground-motive of CFR?

    Second Way of Critique in Science, especially Social Science

    This has implications for both philosophy and scientific research (in all the sciences). In the social sciences, Dooyeweerd reinterpreted the three transcendental questions as [NC,III,168]:

    Communal Version of Second Way of Critique

    My own interpretation of the third transcendental question in my own field, the sociological field of information systems, is that the third transcendental question is best thought of as the community's activity in discussing, critiquing and refining the findings offered by the operation of questions 1 and 2. This does not concern itself with an individual's critical reflection on I-ness -- which I have always found unhelpful because most of my theoretical thought is carried on without it and if these are transcendental conditions for theoretical thought then I would expect to find myself doing it.

    Think about on what basis this communal critique is done (or, if you prefer, self-critique). Typically, the researcher will publish their findings in a journal and thereby invite critique and further refinement, which is itself published as subsequent papers. A conversation ensues. Much critique is related to transcendental question 1, such as "In their survey, the author has asked only a limited range of questions, and in a restricted context; here is a larger study in a different culture, and it broadens out their theory." Some critique is related to transcendental question 2, such as "The author does not analyse correctly; here is a better analysis."

    All critique, however, presupposes meaningfulness. A critique must be deemed relevant by the community, and a defender of the original finding might argue, "But that criticism is irrelevant." Then a debate arises, about what kinds of critique are relevant. Here is a fictitious but plausible sequence of a debate about a particular finding. The first critic of the original paper might question the very approach taken by the researchers:

    "The authors take a positivist approach, which ignores meaning, values and norms; they ought to take an interpretivist approach, which is sensitive to these."

    The original authors or those who support them might reply, defending their original research by reference to something normative or meaningful to research itself:

    "But an interpretivist approach cannot give rigorous results; only a positivist approach can do that."

    To which the critic might respond by questioning the meaningfulness of their norm:

    "But rigour without relevance is meaningless. Only an interpretivist approach can give full relevance, because of the diversity of factors that are meaningful."

    Then another discussant might enter the debate with a deeper philosophical opinion, which tries to embrace both sides of the debate:

    "It is well-known that there is an incommensurability between rigour and relevance; you cannot have them both."

    Here the debate has reached a point that almost nobody in the community would question, a shared agreement about some fundamental 'fact'. This 'fact' is what gives meaning to the entire debate. In this example, the rigour-relevance incommensurability is an expression of the Humanist ground-motive of Nature-Freedom, which is what Dooyeweerd would think of as an Origin of Meaning.

    (Note, his Origin of Meaning is not God the Creator, but rather what we presuppose to be an Origin of temporal diversity of meaningfulness, which itself has its origin in God. By Origin of Meaning, here Dooyeweerd means the communally agreed starting point at which all arguments ultimately stop. The innovation Dooyeweerd made was to suggest a different ground-motive as an alternative Origin of Meaning, the Biblical ground-motive of creation, fall and redemption.)

    Enriching Critical Discourse with CFR

    So, for example, further progress may be made in the above debate by adopting a different ground-motive, which opens up to the community different kinds of presuppositions. For example, a Reformational Scholar might use Dooyeweerd to contribute the following (note, it's longer because it needs to introduce things that are new to the community of thought):

    "The incommensurability between rigour and relevance is only apparent, not real. It is based on a common but fruitless presupposition of the opposition between nature and freedom found in the Nature-freedom ground-motive. If we instead take Creation-Fall-redemption ground-motive, as Dooyeweerd [1955] does, then we are able to recognise distinct aspects which are spheres of meaning and law, and thus better able to cope with diversity of meaning. This enables us to welcome all kinds of meaning (relevance) and yet to separate them out and treat each kind in a rigorous way, according to the kind of rigour suited to it."

    (Note: the quoted pieces above are not the actual text of the debate, but a very brief summary of entire papers published.)

    This, I believe, is something Dooyeweerd was meaning when he formulated his third transcendental question, at least in the context of doing science rather than philosophy. Such debate rests on presuppositions and commitments of a religious nature.

    Basden [2011] has tried to employ this view of Dooyeweerd's transcendental questions in an attempt to find a basis for integrating positivist, interpretivist and socio-critical approaches.


    Some Reflections

    The Importance of Meaningfulness

    All three of the transcendental problems of the second critique may be seen as rooted in, and presupposing meaningfulness, as abstraction of meaningfulness, synthesis of meaningfulness and origin of meaningfulness. More specifically ...

    Problem 1 [NC,I, 41] is about abstraction of what is meaningful. Whereas in the pre-theoretical attitude we are fully immersed in reality, in the theoretical attitude, we 'stand over against' it (Gegenstand relationship) by abstracting aspect(s) of interest. As a stronger version of interpretation-meaning, it targets the aspect(s) of interest, selecting them for study and ignoring others, to provide data for research; sciences like physics, psychology and sociology may be characterized as targeting different aspects. Clouser [2005] usefully differentiates lower abstraction (awareness of aspects of things) from higher abstraction (focus on aspects themselves). In all this, aspects are ways of being meaningful, and the Gegenstand may be seen as our chosen meaningfulness, and Dooyeweerd calls abstraction a "setting-asunder" of the coherence of meaning [NC,I, 33].

    Transcendental problem 2 [NC,I, 45] is about synthesis of rationalities. A rationality is a way of making sense, and sense-making involves understanding the meaningfulness of an aspect. So each aspect defines a distinct rationality. Example: In arguing for distinct rationalities, Winch [1958] wrote, "In science, for example, it would be illogical to refuse to be bound by the results of a properly carried out experiment; in religion it would be illogical to suppose that one could pit one's strength against God's."

    Transcendental problem 3 [NC,I, 52] is about critical self-reflection. Dooyeweerd's answer is that this must make reference to an Origin of Meaning (meaningfulness). In philosophy this is linked with "Philosopher know thyself" while in scientific research it is found in critique of research contributions [Basden 2011a].

    Discussion of the Two Ways of Critique

    First, we can thank Dooyeweerd for coming up with two ways of critique, not just one. Most thinkers present only a single thread of argument in support of their beliefs, but Dooyeweerd presents us with two. Two witnesses are always better than one:

    both independently point to the religious root of theoretical thought, and that theoretical thinking is fundamentally non-neutral. This means that even if we find Way 1, based on a notion of philosophy, does not suit us, then we might find Way 2 better, based on a notion of what theoretical thinking itself is. And vice versa.

    But, as we might expect, both Ways exhibit problems. One problem with the First Way of Critique is that it depends on Dooyeweerd's view that philosophy is concerned with totality of Meaning. It is widely agreed that philosophy is concerned with totality, but not totality of Meaning. Most presuppose Existence rather than Meaning. Dooyeweerd's First Way was published first in the 1930s, and in response to acknowledging this supposed weakness, and various other criticisms, Dooyeweerd developed Way 2. Various criticisms made of Way 1 are outlined by Choi.

    There have also been criticisms of this Second Way of Critique, again as outlined by Choi. Whether we agree with them or not, it is useful at least to notice that Way 2 presupposes two things. One is the notion of aspects that are 'non-logical', but this is not an unreasonable assumption. The other is the neo-Kantian assumption that logical thinking operates by way of a Gegenstand, i.e. it creates an antithesis that must be synthesized. Way 2 is also more difficult to understand than Way 1.

    One problem that arises from Way 2 is that it seems to preclude any theory about theory itself, since logical thinking involves an opposition between the logical and non-logical. At first sight, at least, it is self-obviously not the case that we cannot have theory of theory; surely we can and do! Dooyeweerd explicitly says that the logical cannot be Gegenstand for itself (e.g. NC II:463). But, in other places, he does talk about theory of theory and assume that such is possible (e.g. NC I:40). This seems an unresolved problem. But the problem seems to stem from the neo-Kantian assumption rather than how Dooyeweerd uses it. So, if we can replace the neo-Kantian assumption, perhaps Dooyeweerd's Way 2 still stands.

    Alternative Versions

    One way of doing this is Clouser's alternative exposition of Way 2; it seems to overcome this problem. In place of Gegenstand, Clouser speaks of isolation of an aspect, the severing of ties with the other aspects, as the inevitable result of logical thinking (he calls it higher abstraction). Since nothing - neither an aspect nor any entity - can be fully nor truly understood without reference to all others, this isolation inevitably results in loss of meaning and thus distortion. If this is the source of the problem, then there is no difficulty about having a theory about theory.

    Another attempt has been made by Strauss [1983]. He proposed that theoretical thinking is little different from the logical subject-object relationship that we find in everyday living, that is analytical functioning. But it is not clear that this is adequate since it confuses theoretical thinking with analytical distinction-making.

    Geertsema [2000] has suggested, after discussing both Ways of Critique, that a modified version of Way 1 is preferable. He modifies Way 1 to give the central place to the human thinker rather than to philosophy itself.

    My Original Rendering of 2nd Way of Critique

    [I originally explained TC2 as follows. I now believe it contains some misunderstandings of what Dooyeweerd was trying to get at, but I retain it in case it is my current understanding that is flawed! A.B.]

    References

    Basden A. (2011). Enabling a Kleinian integration of interpretivist and critical-social IS research: The contribution of Dooyeweerd's philosophy. European Journal of Information Systems. 20, 477-489.

    Basden A. 2019. Foundations and Practice of Research : Adventures with Dooyeweerd's Philosophy. Routledge.

    Dooyeweerd H. 1960/2012. In the Twilight of Western Thought, ed. JKA Smith. Paideia Press.

    Geertsema H (2000) "Dooyeweerd's Transcendental Critique: Transforming it Hermeneutically", pp. 83-108 in Strauss DFM, Botting M (eds.), Contemporary Reflections on the Philosophy of Herman Dooyeweerd, The Edwin Mellen Press, New York.

    Geertsema H (2000) "Dooyeweerd's Transcendental Critique: Transforming it Hermeneutically", pp. 111-142 in H. Geerstema Homo Respondens, Paideia Press.

    Strauss DFM (1983) "An analysis of the structure of analysis (The Gegenstand-relation in discussion)" Philosophia Reformata 49:35-56.

    Notes

    [1] Verbrugge ftn: "Wetmatig" in the original. I cannot find an existing English word for it. Prof P A Verburg proposed the use of idionomic - idios: particular or peculiar, and nomos: law). [NB BCW regular, or regulative seems preferable].

    [2] Here 'scientific' seems to mean 'theoretical' in general rather than being of any particular scientific area, which is what we meant at the end of Way 1.


    This page, "http://dooy.info/tc.html", is part of The Dooyeweerd Pages, which explain, explore and discuss Dooyeweerd's interesting philosophy. Questions or comments are very welcome.

    Compiled by Andrew Basden. You may use this material subject to conditions.

    Written on the Amiga with Protext, in the style of classic HTML.

    Created: 16 May 2003. Last updated: 10 June 2003 corrections from comments by Henk Geertsema. 2 August 2004 link to Glenn F's translation. 28 June 2005 new section 'need.another' and quot'n from RSP; contents. 2 July 2009 Bourdieu. 10 July 2010 Revamped tc2, shifting older one to alternatives. 7 August 2012 name-labels on the 3 transcendental questions. 24 March 2015 added section about TC in social sciences and science in general, explaining TQ3 as the debate. 20 April 2015 critique presupposes meaningfulness; rewrote previous entry a bit. 3 September 2015 corrected '../'; rid counter; new .nav, .end. 17 September 2015 added missing ending to answer to TQ3. 17 January 2018 importance of meaningfulness. 31 March 2021 new intro, new section on Dooyeweerd's approach, references; new .end, .nav, bgc. 29 April 2021 Feynman and the problems with experiment. 25 January 2022 Twilight, and example of synthesis. 27 May 2023 On Origins of Meaning; rw intro para on critiques.